Thomson’s Legacy: Relatively Greek
Alexander Greek Thomson Award 2017 - Special Mention

Architecture has long used the analogy of language to
describe a codification of formal gestures or stylistic tropes into a
communicable system of representation for a collective subject. The terms of
this analogy are abstract – form must be intelligible, architectural elements
given symbolic meaning – and it is through this abstraction that a language
begins to be constructed which has a relevance in cultural consciousness.
The classical language of architecture was, until
comparatively recent times, the communicative basis of Western architectural
form. Derived from the classical ideal
of “divine impassibility and beauty residing in pure lines and harmonious
proportions,” this language provided acolytes with the grammatical tools with
which to communicate across historical time, assimilating ideas based on a
correspondence between man, form, and the universe. [1] In
order to be constructive, the principles governing and structuring a language
must be legible to society collectively, not in a deterministic cause and
effect relationship, but in a manner which has the capacity for change and
revision.
For Alexander ‘Greek’ Thomson, the architect behind some of
the most inventive examples of 19th century architectural
production, the common language was that derived from the ‘eternal laws’ with
which he was concerned: “Some people imagine that the rules of architecture are
arbitrary [...] but the fact is, the laws which govern the universe, whether
aesthetical or physical, are the same which govern architecture. We do not
contrive rules; we discover laws. There is such a thing as architectural
truth.”[2]
Contrary to what this statement might seem to suggest,
Thomson was not dogmatic in his application of the formal laws of antiquity. He was as remarkable for his comprehensive
knowledge of the classical language as for his radical use of it. “The promoters of the Greek Revival,” Thomson
believed, had “failed because they could not see through the material into the
laws upon which that architecture rested. They failed to master their style,
and so became its slaves.”[3]
Through his identification of language as tool, as opposed
to language as doctrine, Thomson gave importance to the structural foundation of
this language upon which mutable form could be conceived, and in doing so,
forged a territory in which formal inventiveness and idiosyncrasies could be
incorporated without departure from an elemental stylistic base. His approach was not historicist. Within his work, overarching laws governing
harmony and proportion are conflated with a pictorial sensibility. As John Maule McKean discusses in his 1985
essay ‘The Architectonics and Ideals of Alexander Thomson,’ “in concentrating
on an ideal, via the abstract, [Thomson] did not see history as a great and
gradually developing tapestry to which he could join. Rather, his more transcendental aim was to use
the data of history to reveal essences […] Thomson was innovating in order to
reinforce the intended illusion.”[4]
In pursuit of the underlying structures of architectural
language, the morphological root of the ideal, it would be easy to render architecture
a cloistered, autonomous, discipline. An
understanding of the evolution of architecture based only on an internal,
disciplinary syntax and the delineation of interests seen as intrinsic to
architecture itself, however, negates the wider socio-cultural and political
context in which any building is conceived and constructed. To formulate this understanding would require
history to be viewed as fragmentary, as a heterogeneous collection of episodes,
a stance which diverges from an account of history composed of models from
which a language could be deciphered.
In his analysis of Johann Joachim Winckelmann’s 1794 description
of the Belvedere Torso, Jacques Rancière discusses the formation of an
autonomous history of art as being subject to a historical basis for the
conception of collective life. The
fundamental contingency this engenders becomes critical in developing a
disciplinary autonomy which retains cultural relevance. It is within this relationship, within relative
autonomy, that the idea of legacy is situated.
Rancière describes the convergence of the once fragmentary
histories of objects and ideas from antiquity, uniting the theories of the
ideal and the actuality of the archaeological real into a singular totality. Through bringing these strands together, the
totality is given critical autonomy through the internalised relation of the
objects to each other, with the ideal as interlocutor. Critical autonomy is used here to describe
meaning within this totality; disciplinary autonomy derives meaning in relation
to the other, to the collective. Rancière
employs history as a concept to generate the contingencies required for a disciplinary
autonomy to exist:
“History does not come to take the constituted reality of art as its
object. It constitutes this reality
itself. In order for there to be a
history of art, art must exist as a reality in itself, distinct from the lives
of artists and the histories of monuments […] Yet reciprocally, for art to
exist as the sensible environment for works, history must exist as the form of
intelligence of collective life.”[5]
History, in this context, represents a collective subject. It occupies the realm of shared values, the
public realm, and signifies the commonality between “those who draw the
blueprints for collective buildings, those who cut the stones for those
buildings, those who preside over ceremonies, and those who participate in
them.”[6]
It is inherently a product of its environment
and becomes the intermediary between collectivity and the autonomous space of individual
imagination. It occupies the critical
liminal position.
The reciprocity which is pivotal to this lays plain the
fundamentally dialectical nature of autonomy.
Whilst Rancière’s discussion specifically deals with the history of art,
an understanding of the contingent relationships governing architecture is similarly
significant. To posit an absolute
autonomy of architecture would necessitate dissolving the dialectic we have
just constructed, removing architectural form from its cultural and societal
context. Architecture is a repository
for culture: it holds social memory; it works to bring together iconography and
semiotic issues with material. This most
powerful social aspect of architecture, its capacity to engage with and be
engaged by its context, cannot be excluded in order to form an argument for an
autonomous discipline. Relative autonomy
on the other hand, an autonomy contingent on place and time, on politics and
socio-cultural patterns, on geographical specificities and a global transfer of
knowledge, constructs the framework to bring these divergent issues into a productive
relationship. Considered in relation to
the work of an architect, a building, or an architectural object, this leads to
a far more complex conception of legacy.
The
concept of a formal legacy within architecture is necessarily auto-reflexive.Key
to the relevance of form or element in a time past its initial present is the
understanding of formal legacy as re-presenting objects, as opposed to
presenting artefacts. What distinguishes
the two positions is the nature of the formal.
When considered as object, the formal is relational. Specific to a place and time, the object embodies
the contingencies and inherent ambiguities resulting from its
re-presentation. As artefact, the formal
is conceived as purely self-referential and self-sufficient − the expression of
an internal logic.
Thomson aimed to express an ideal and this is how his legacy
should be thought. Elements from
antiquity are re-presented as objects in their own right rather than as
facsimile or artefacts content with reifying fragments from the past. Andor Gomme and David Walker in their 1968
book The Architecture of Glasgow conclude:
“None of Thomson’s direct successors really knew how to benefit from his
example or to understand what he had done to the remnants of the classical
tradition. Like all great artists who
have inherited a tradition formed into a different context of civilization,
Thomson not only absorbed it into himself but adapted it and reformed it into
something which could once again be a living and expressive medium.”[7]
The amalgamation of the manifold historiographies and social
influences orbiting architectural discourse can never result in a unified
theory or absolute truth. Legacy, as a
result, does not exist within a closed autonomy of form but in the heteronomy
of architectural production and experience. It is intertwined with a temporal
and contextual understanding.
From the banks of the Nile 1500 years BCE and the rocky
hills of Mycenae and Athens a century later, formal legacies have been
transmitted across millennia and continents and have been reimagined for a
different place. Thomson’s radical use of
the language of antiquity combined an articulation and redistribution of its
elements and with a formal inventiveness and revised semiotics befitting his
own time. He produced architecture which
displays an exceptional originality and his buildings have come to act as pivotal
references in their own right. Through
abstraction, not facsimile, but re-presentation.
[1] Rancière, J., Aisthesis (London: Verso, 2013). p.2
[2] Thomson, A., in Stamp, G., The Light of Truth and Beauty (Glasgow: The Alexander Thomson Society, 1999). p.68 [3] Ibid. p.147
[4]McKean, J.M., ‘The Architectonics and Ideals of Alexander Thomson’ in AA Files No. 9(London: AA Publications, 1985). p.32
[5] Rancière, J., Op. Cit., pp. 13-14. The ‘sensible’ for Rancière is the condition of perception, founded on a division of subjectivity that is partly formed within the collective social sphere, and partly by individual experience. [6] Rancière, J., Ibid.
[7] Gomme, A., & Walker D., as quoted in Mordaunt Crook, J., ‘More Thomsonian than Greek’ AA Files No. 9 (London: AA Publications, 1985). p.84